An everyday account of witnessing

This paper presents a discussion of an everyday ontology of witnessing drawing on the writings of Martin Heidegger, cognitive science and presence research. We begin by defining witnessing: to witness we must be present; and that which is witnessed must be available.

This paper presents a discussion of an everyday ontology of witnessing drawing on the writings of Martin Heidegger, cognitive science and presence research. We begin by defining witnessing: to witness we must be present; and that which is witnessed must be available.

Turner P. "An everyday account of witnessing"

Witnessing is distinguished from perceiving in that it implies and requires a record (a representation) of what has been perceived. Presence and availability are (relatively) uncontroversial but finding a place for representation, which is a classically dualistic concept, in an ontological account potentially presents difficulties. We address this problem by recognising that being available, ready-to-hand and proximal can also serve to represent the very thing being witnessed.

AI & Society, Journal for Knowledge, Culture an Communication. Special issue Witnessed Presence. Volume 27, Number 1, February 2012
Online available at: Springerlink.com:
DOI 10.1007/s00146-011-0323-9

Expand selection Contract selection

Witnessing as a mode of being in the world

This paper considers what is involved when we witness an event from an (everyday) ontological perspective, by specifically applying, at least initially, the language and philosophy of Martin Heidegger. The use of ‘everyday’ is important because it distinguishes his flavour of ontology from other classical accounts which are concerned with getting to the ‘core’ of phenomena or as Husserl put it “[to] the things themselves”.

This paper considers what is involved when we witness an event from an (everyday) ontological perspective, by specifically applying, at least initially, the language and philosophy of Martin Heidegger. The use of ‘everyday’ is important because it distinguishes his flavour of ontology from other classical accounts which are concerned with getting to the ‘core’ of phenomena or as Husserl put it “[to] the things themselves”.

This everyday or existential ontology is an account of being referenced on the everyday experiences of people (Dasein)[1] rather than to an abstract philosophical notion.

We begin with the simple premise that to witness requires Dasein to be present. Therefore to understand witnessing we must understand that most important and necessary pre-condition, namely, that Dasein is present in the world. Indeed from a Heideggerian perspective, Dasein, by definition, means being present in the world. However we immediately encounter a raft of difficulties as the more widely accepted definitions of being present in the world as proposed by the ‘presence research’ community – (see the International Society for Presence Research - ispr.info) typically treat it as it were a consequence of experiencing virtual reality technology or enjoying an immersive experience (e.g. a trip to the local IMAX cinema), rather than being a primordial condition in its own right. Thus presence research has sought to understand the conditions required to create a sense of presence and to measure it thereafter. Presence has been treated as a commodity which can be increased, diminished, broken (interrupted) and otherwise manipulated (e.g. Brogni et al., 2006; Freeman et al., 2007 – among many others). However, I argue that taking being present in the world as a primordial state means that (a) we regard it as a propensity or readiness to act or perceive and (b) it is geared towards the world and all that it comprises (more of this in the next section). In treating presence as a readiness to engage with the world, to cope with the world, to deal with the world and to witness events, people and things, then witnessing itself becomes a consequence of being present in the world. Heidegger describes this readiness in his History of the Concept of Time as: ‘the background of … primary familiarity, which itself is not conscious or intended but is rather present in [an] unprominent way’ (189). To witness does not simply mean we were in a particular place at a particular time when such and such a thing happened. For example, I, with millions of others, witnessed the first (and subsequent) Moon landings. I have a clear memory of sitting up late (in the UK) and witnessing it on TV. I had followed the launch of Apollo XI, the broadcasts from outer space and the eagerly awaited the landing. To witness is then not so much about co-location or contemporaneity but one of being prepared, and of being ready. Witnessing can then be recognised as a mode of being in the world.

------------------------------
Note 1: A quick word of explanation on Dasein before we continue. The German word Dasein (lit. being-there) is traditionally left un- translated and is taken to stand for ‘human being’ and is usually printed in a different font–like this. Being undefined, Dasein is recognized as being contingent or seen as a ‘placeholder’ for ‘who’ and ‘what’ we are.

Expand selection Contract selection

Presence, ready-to-hand and representation

Treating witnessing in this way has a number of interesting consequences for the premises upon which it stands:

Treating witnessing in this way has a number of interesting consequences for the premises upon which it stands:

Firstly, it challenges the treatment of presence as the mere product of human information processing, a point well made by Riva and his colleagues (Riva et al. 2004). They have argued that presence either evolved for no particular purpose (that is, it is an emergent or serendipitous property of the nervous system) or it has some evolutionary advantage. In examining the latter alternative, they note that “the appearance of the sense of presence allows the nervous system to solve a key problem for its survival: how to differentiate between internal and external states”. This biological / evolutionary perspective tells us one further thing about presence, namely that it is an active state (or process) and that this activity is directed at the world. Being directed at the world means that presence is intentional. That is, it has the property of being about something rather than some kind of free floating mental state. Intentionality connects our mental states (and bodies) to the world and when we witness something we ‘inherit’ this intentionality, so that the psychological and physiological states associated with witnessing are similarly intentional.

Secondly, this consideration of witnessing also foregrounds the importance of understanding the properties of that which is being witnessed. Presence research, in the main, has tended to treat the make up of the worlds (real or virtual) in which we find ourselves present as content factors (e.g. Fencott, 1999; Lessiter et al., 2001; Schubert et al. 2001, Slater, 2003; Baños et al., 2004; Nunez and Blake, 2006 among other). Ijsselsteijn et al. (2000) have proposed examples of content factors as including objects, actors, events, interactivity, autonomy of environment and agents, reactions of others and the nature of tasks (conducted in a virtual environment). In contrast, and from this ontological perspective, we recognise that to be witnessed things, people and events are required to be available. By availability we mean, within reach, proximal or as Heidegger (1927/1962) famously put it, ready-to-hand. Thus we can feel closer to our own spouse, who might be hundreds of kilometres away, on our cell phone than we do to a passenger sitting next to us on a train. This account of ‘readiness-to-hand’ is based on his observation that we do not encounter entities as discrete objects or as substances but as part of a meaningful network of things we can use (Heidegger calls them tools and equipment), exploit or engage while other beings which are not immediately available to us are said to be present-at-hand.[2]

Finally, witnessing is different from perceiving in that the former involves the creation of a representation of what we witness but this in itself presents us with a problem. The language and concepts we have used so far have been ontological which has no place for the representational. Our solution to this is to adopt and extend Clark’s distinction between strong and weak representation. We propose that, like Clark, those things (other beings) which are available can also serve as a kind of external memory or as a weak ‘representation’. This recalls both Dreyfus’ observation that ‘The best representation of the world is [ …] the world itself’ (Dreyfus, 2002) and that most ancient of mnemonics the method of loci.

We now consider each of these points in a little more detail beginning with a discussion of presence.

------------------------------
Note 2: To describe present-at-hand as unavailable is a simplification but one which I do not believe misleads. Dreyfus (1991), for example, in his commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, distinguishes between available and unavailable as being aspects of readiness-to- hand and uses the term occurrentness to describe being present-at- hand (occurrentness also having two states or modes). While these are important distinctions I do not think that they are germane to the current discussion here.

Expand selection Contract selection

Being Present

Presence has been (historically) defined as the sense of “being there” (Held and Durlach, 1992) and “the subjective experience of being in one place or environment, even when one is physically situated in another” (Witmer & Singer, 1998).

Presence has been (historically) defined as the sense of “being there” (Held and Durlach, 1992) and “the subjective experience of being in one place or environment, even when one is physically situated in another” (Witmer & Singer, 1998).

Figure 1: Proto presence (reproduced, with kind permission, from Riva et al., 2004, p. 409)

It has also generally been treated as comprising multiple dimension, for example, Lombard and Ditton (1997) have identified six different aspects including: the sense of having been transported, of being immersed and of being in a social medium while Schloerb (1995) distinguishes between ‘subjective’ and ‘objective’ presence. Presence has been theorised about factor-analytically (Schubert et al., 2001); has been treated as a biological phenomenon (e.g. Revonsuo, 2006); as a consequence of evolutionary pressures (e.g. Waterworth and Waterworth, 2001; Riva et al., 2004) and as an embodied phenomenon (e.g. Biocca, 1997). Presence research has received relatively little philosophical consideration, an exception being Zahorik and Jenison (1998) who, as with the current discussion, relate it to Heidegger’s being-in-the-world. More recent definitions have tended to treat presence as a conjunction of different psychological and physiological states. For example, Slater (2004) has made a strong case for presence comprising engagement with elements in the real or virtual environment and spatial presence - the sense or experience of being located somewhere specific.

In contrast to these positions, as we have already noted, we propose that presence is a primordial state – in that it cannot be reduced to more primitive states – which we define as the readiness to respond echoing Riva and his colleague’s evolutionary account (discussed above). While theirs is an interesting and potentially compelling argument it presents two related problems for our account of witnessing.

Firstly, for Riva et al. the environment is an undifferentiated “black box” (or grey smudge) - please see figure 1 which has been reproduced from their original paper. This lack of differentiation is at odds with our position regarding the availability of that which is witnessed, Gibson’s account of affordance, current ecological psychological thinking, their own account of organisms actively solving problems and, not least, people’s everyday experience of being in the world.

In short, we experience the world as a meaningful Gestalt and not as a source of undifferentiated sensory data. We daily demonstrate our presence (and familiarity with the world - see Turner, 2008a and 2008b for a fuller discussion of familiarity) by coping with situations, tools and objects by our understanding of world as a coherent whole. For example, Heidegger has argued that when we encounter a room we experience it as a whole, as a Gestalt (though he actually uses the Kantian term manifold) “… from which the individual pieces of furniture and what is in the room stand out’ (Heidegger, 1985 section 187). From there ‘our practical everyday orientation’ allows us to cope with whatever is there. Our familiarity with these everyday worlds ensures that when we return home we see the kitchen, one’s spouse, the cat, the unpaid bills and that half bottle of wine from last night. We do not perceive a jumble of surfaces, strangers, printed paper, animals and half-empty bottles. We skilfully engage with this world by walking into the kitchen, embracing our spouse, feeding the cat, ignoring the bills and pouring a glass of wine. We actively engage with the world rather than merely processing of sensory information. But more than this, as we have argued elsewhere (Turner, 2007) presence, by this view, is necessarily transitive – that is, it needs a predicate. We are present somewhere specific; we are engaged with those things which are available, and we witness specific events.
A second issue concerns the direction of the arrow in the figure which appears to portrays people as passive (and possibly puzzled) information processors whereas we have argued that presence is intentional which would suggest that the arrow points the other way, i.e. from the individual to the environment. It was Franz Brentano (1838-1917) who revived interest in intentionality, St. Thomas Aquinas having introduced the concept in the 13th century, by recognising that most of our mental states (including attitudes, affective states and so forth) are directed towards things and events in the world. Brentano defined intentionality as the main characteristic of mental phenomena, by which they could be distinguished from physical phenomena (Brentano, 1995). The word itself is derived from the Latin tendere, which means being directed towards some goal or some thing.[3] Accepting that presence is intentional suggests that the arrow in figure 1 may be pointing in the wrong direction.

So what is intentionality? We now consider two contrasting though mutually sympathetic accounts. The first is based on the work of Merleau-Ponty which takes as its starting point our corporality and the second draws on the neurological work of Walter Freeman.

------------------------------
Note 3: The everyday use of the term intentionality meaning intending, intentions or motivations such as the intention to drink a cup of tea should be distinguished from the concept’s philosophical sense.

Expand selection Contract selection

Intentionality

Merleau-Ponty (1945/1962) developed the concept of intentionality to include what we would now describe as embodiment. He argues that it is only though our lived bodies do we have access to what he describes as the “primary world”. Without our bodies there could be no world thus the concept of the lived body is central to his account of (corporeal) intentionality and replaces the usual Cartesian mind-body distinction.

Merleau-Ponty (1945/1962) developed the concept of intentionality to include what we would now describe as embodiment. He argues that it is only though our lived bodies do we have access to what he describes as the “primary world”. Without our bodies there could be no world thus the concept of the lived body is central to his account of (corporeal) intentionality and replaces the usual Cartesian mind-body distinction.

Figure 2: The dynamic architecture of the limbic system – redrawn after Freeman, 1999 p. 150

The world and the lived body together form what Merleau-Ponty calls an intentional arc which binds the body to the world. For example, the movement of the lived body actually creates (produces) existential space. It is not, however, the “objective” movement of the body as such, instead it is the experience of this movement, “Far from my body’s being for me no more than a fragment of space, there would be no space at all for me if I had no body”. To feel our body (kinaesthesia) feeling its surroundings is not merely an exercise in self-reflection but the means by which we, as Merleau-Ponty puts it, “prehend” the world. This kinaesthetic feedback is the means by which we both objectify the world and orient ourselves within it. To orient ourselves is to adopt an external point or frame of reference. However, Merleau-Ponty also recognised the role of the world (environment) when he wrote, “To move one’s body is to aim at things through it; it is to allow oneself to respond to their call” (ibid). This intentional arc is then the knowledge of how to act in a way that coheres with one’s environment bringing body and world together. But this is more than just being physically present in the world: “the life of consciousness - cognitive life, the life of desire or perceptual life - is subtended by an intentional arc which projects round about us our past, our future, our human setting, our physical, ideological and moral situation”. So, from this reading of Merleau-Ponty, witnessing is an act of construction and a part of an intentional arc binding us to the world.
The second treatment of intentionality draws on the work of Walter Freeman, the celebrated neuro-scientist, who has described the philosophical treatment of intentionality as “anaemic”. Instead he describes intentionality as ‘the process of the brain in action’ (Freeman, 1999 p.18) and ‘having the properties of unity, wholeness and intent (the intension of taking in by stretching forth) ...” - the parallel with Merleau-Ponty (cf. Dreyfus, 1996) is striking.

In his Society of Brains Freeman sees intentionality as an outward push and likens it to what Darwin called “nerve force”; and what Bergson called “élan vitale”. This outward push is mediated by the neural circuits represented in figure 2. Freeman observes that studies of the origin of ‘spontaneous’ background activity of cortex place it in the mutual excitation among neurons which can spill over into the restlessness. The schematic flow of activity locates the intentional arc in the forebrain by which purposive behaviours are generated.

Writing in Society of Brains he notes that the state of the brain at any moment, may be conceived of as a spatiotemporal pattern, which is the result of the interaction of the motor, sensory and associational areas creates. This pattern is transmitted to the brain stem and spinal cord, with a number of feedback loops acting as a control mechanism. Additional feedback is delivered proprioceptively and monitors action and evaluates the performance with respect to the intent. The above architecture provides for a neurological basis for intentionality.

Having considered presence as an outward, intentional push we now turn to the object of its “attention” in the environment.

Expand selection Contract selection

Availability

Heidegger notes that our primary interaction with beings[4] is through use or by communication if human beings are concerned. Dreyfus describes this interaction as ‘skilful engagement’ (Dreyfus, 1991). Dreyfus and Wrathall (2005, p. 4) in their introduction to a collection of essays on Heidegger write, “we first encounter worldly things as available.

Heidegger notes that our primary interaction with beings[4] is through use or by communication if human beings are concerned. Dreyfus describes this interaction as ‘skilful engagement’ (Dreyfus, 1991). Dreyfus and Wrathall (2005, p. 4) in their introduction to a collection of essays on Heidegger write, “we first encounter worldly things as available.

Something is available when (1) it is defined in terms of its place in a context of equipment, typical activities in which it is used, and typical purposes and goals for which it is used, and (2) it lends itself to such use readily and easily without need for reflection. The core case of availability is an item of equipment that we know how to use and that transparently lends itself to use”. For Heidegger, all human activity is located in vast, inter-related array of tools and equipment. For example, I am writing this at my desk, in my office sitting on a chair. On the desk is my Apple™ iMac, to the right of which is a wireless mouse (I am right-handed). Immediately before me is a wireless keyboard, to my left is a coffee cup, a notebook, a book on Heidegger, and a pile of academic papers. By the above definition, all of these items are available to me, as they are proximal and ready-to-hand and comprise one of my working environments. However, in addition to these physically proximal entities, I have a high speed Internet link which (by way of a click or two) connects me to online databases located on other continents. I also have access to a range of network services located through the University – but exactly where I really have no idea. So, readiness-to-hand is a matter of experience, or of how I encounter the world rather than location in physical space. Indeed readiness-to-hand is also a very good description of the affordances available to Dasein (Gibson, 1986).
This Heideggerian perspective moves us away from thinking in terms of listing the discrete properties of things, to how we encounter these things as tool-beings (Harman, 2002). Re-casting this slightly, we can say that we encounter the world as a network of inter-connected affordances (Turner, 2005). Gibson describes an affordances in a similar kind of way, for example, when he writes “An affordance cuts across the dichotomy of subjective-objective and helps us to understand its inadequacy. It is equally a fact of the environment and a fact of behaviour. It is both physical and psychical, yet neither. An affordance points both ways, to the environment and to the observer” (Gibson, 1986, p.129). Thus affordance is not a property of a tool but how we encounter that tool. While this all appears rather functional, and rather confined to manual labour, tools for enjoying ourselves and for having fun are no different. However, since Gibson first introduced the concept, it has been developed in a variety of ways particularly by ecological psychology (e.g. Warren, 1984; Turvey, 1992; Stoffregen, 2000) and human-computer interaction communities (e.g. Norman, 1988; 1999; Gaver, 1991; 1992; de Souza, 1993; de Souza et al., 2000 among very many). Hartson (2003), for example, has proposed a four-fold division of affordance for the purposes of designing for interaction. These four categories are (a) cognitive affordance; (b) physical affordance; (c) sensory affordance and finally, (d) functional affordance. This four-fold classification maps onto corresponding functions: for example, physical affordance is synonymous with utility, while sensory affordances include such things as colour and contrast.
Affordance also appears in the academic reporting of anthropology, for example, Cole (1996) identifies a range of affordance offered by a variety of mediating artefacts including the life stories of recovering alcoholics in Alcoholics Anonymous meetings (affording rehabilitation), patients’ charts in a hospital setting (affording medical diagnosis) and poker chips (affording gambling). Cole notes that mediating artefacts embody their own “developmental histories” which is reflects their use.
Finally, there is also substantial evidence from studies of the neural basis of perception and action, for example, positron emission tomography has shown that those parts of the brain responsible for motor representation are activated in response to the perception of the affordances of objects. Grèzes and Decety (2002, p. 212) concluding that “perception of objects automatically affords actions that can be made towards them” – cf. Freeman. It may be that availability has its origins with the ways in which we first encounter the world. Although Heidegger does not address the issue of our corporeality or embodiment, it is evident that we first encounter the limits of the scope of what is available, proximal and handy by way of our bodies. This progresses from encountering our own hands (through, for example, sucking our thumbs) and the body of our mother to all manner of external objects (beings) to the internalisation of these actions to form what we experience as cognition – if Piaget is to be believed. So, it is likely that embodiment is at the root of what we find available.

So far we have suggested that two of the requirements of witnessing are complementary: the readiness to encounter and the offers to encounter[5] presented to Dasein. In the next section we consider the issue of the representation of the witnessed event.

------------------------------
Note 4: Heidegger’s ontology requires us to regard all things in the world as beings–e.g. chair-beings, book-beings, macbook-pro-beings, pencil- beings, cup-of-coffee-beings. While this is, to most people, unfamiliar it does remove the fundamental Cartesian assumption of subject and object. Instead, we encounter other beings but this is not to suggest that these beings have intelligence or sentience but that an everyday ontological examination of chairs would be into their chair-ness for me. The everydayness of a chair is its availability for sitting on, or standing on, or for barricading a door with and so on.
Note 5: Lewin (1936) referred to affordances as Aufforderungscharakter or invitation character.

Expand selection Contract selection

Representation

At the outset of this paper we identified representation as being one of the characteristics of witnessing and the biggest problem for this everyday ontological account. At its simplest, witnessing is distinguished from perception by virtue of the record or representation that the former implies.

At the outset of this paper we identified representation as being one of the characteristics of witnessing and the biggest problem for this everyday ontological account. At its simplest, witnessing is distinguished from perception by virtue of the record or representation that the former implies.

There is, of course, a large body of psychological research which has considered the nature of witnessing and ‘eye witness’ accounts (for example Loftus, 1975; 1979; Loftus et al. 1989) and, of course, our episodic and autobiographical memories are memories of events (episodes) we have witnessed or in which we have participated (see for example, Conway, 2001; 2003). However representation is used in many different ways by the very many different disciplines which write and reason about it. Clark (1997a; 1997b) has made considerable efforts to unpick and clarify the nature of representation, which he defines as “information-bearing internal states”. Rejecting the extreme non-representational, radical embodied accounts (e.g. Dreyfus, 2002; Chemero, 2009), he distinguishes between “weak” representations and “strong” representations (Clark and Grush, 1999). Strong representation is what most people would regard as genuine representation – the stuff of cognitive processes. Strong representations are further defined as being “de-coupled” from the immediate world and thus stand for things when they are removed from us (or us from them) . Here we see representation as re-presentation (to present again). In contrast, weak representation refer to internal states bearing information about an external object (event or person) but only when that object is available, proximal and ready-to-hand. Weak representations are found in what Clark describes as “information and control systems” rather than information-bearing states per se and as such they facilitate our responsiveness to the environment (e.g. fight or flight). In the next section we briefly consider strong representation (from the perspective of everyday memory) before doing the same for weak representation.

Strong representation

Bearing witness is mediated, it is derived and necessarily relies on the manipulation of a (strong) representation of that which was witnessed. The extent of this manipulation is a matter of concern not only to academic psychologists, but to journalists, lawyers, historians and so forth. Curiously, the study of memory has not, until relatively recently, been concerned with real world memories: instead it has focussed on laboratory–based studies of how many items can be remembered, or how quickly they are forgotten. These laboratory-based studies, which have broadly followed the protocols established by Ebbinghaus in the 19th century, predominated until Neisser dismissed the work on memory of the previous 100 years of research as worthless for failing to answer “the important questions about memory” and called for a shift to the “realistic” study of memory (Neisser, 1978). Since Neisser’s outburst, everyday memory research has become well established and there has been a growing number of studies on such varied topics as autobiographical memory, eyewitness testimony, prospective memory, “flashbulb” memory, memory for action, memory for faces, memory for places and so forth (e.g. Cohen, 1989). There is now a substantial body of psychological evidence relating to the recall of witnessed events which variously show that these memories are re-constructed (e.g. Burt et al., 2001); are subject to distortion and manipulation (e.g. Loftus, 1979; Loftus et al. 1989; Braun et al., 2002); and are story-like or schematic in their structure (Bartlett, 1932; Hasher, 1983; Conway, 2001; 2003). As this is so well documented and so well established we will leave the discussion at this point and move on to a consideration of the less well known role of weak representation in witnessing.

Weak representation

The idea of the outside world acting as part of our cognition has received sustained attention in recent years, which have seen the creation of enactive, dynamic, situated and distributed accounts of cognition (indeed this is an almost unmanageably long list). All, to a greater or lesser extent, identify and implicate a role of some feature or aspect of ‘not us’ in our memories, problem solving, reasoning and so forth. In many respects, however, these are still largely cognitive accounts. In contrast, for Clark, weak representations do not count as genuine representations, that is, they do not stand for anything. Weak representations only become active when the individual is engaged with the world (while, correspondingly, strong representations are active when we are disengaged from the world). Weak representation provide us (Dasein) with rapid feedback about proximal objects enabling us to respond to them effectively (there is substantial evidence that it is the striate motor cortex is responsible for encoding information related to proximal objects). Clark has also noted that if the source object of a weak representation becomes distal (or absent) the representation becomes unavailable. At this point we propose extending this account. We suggest that the affordances of the entities themselves may actually serve as an external representation, as a kind of recursive memory of themselves. This point can be illustrated with a simple, everyday example. We all use shopping lists, online calendar, diaries, our smart phones and notebooks as media for the external representation of what we need to remember or for plans of various sorts. In other words we exploit the affordance of notebooks as memory prosthetics. However we can also use the affordances of objects themselves as reminders of the things we need to remember. So, the night before we are due to travel (assuming an early morning departure) we will put passports, travel documents and so forth in plain sight. I, for one, will put important documents in the path which I am bound to take as I leave my home. The very sight of these objects as they become available (as I leave the house) provides me with the necessary information to act appropriately (i.e. remembering to take them with me).
A very similar technique is used by police forces in the ‘re-creation’ of crimes by populating the crime scene with people, objects and events which are ‘close’ (proximal) to the people, objects and events involved.

Expand selection Contract selection

Being present in the world

"Not a whit, we defy augury: there's a special providence in the fall of a sparrow. If it be now, 'tis not to come; if it be not to come, it will be now; if it be not now, yet it will come: the readiness is all: since no man has aught of what he leaves, what is't to leave betimes?"

Hamlet, scene II

"Not a whit, we defy augury: there's a special providence in the fall of a sparrow. If it be now, 'tis not to come; if it be not to come, it will be now; if it be not now, yet it will come: the readiness is all: since no man has aught of what he leaves, what is't to leave betimes?"

Hamlet, scene II

This has been a wide ranging discussion bringing together neurological studies, ontological perspectives and cognitive science. The argument was based on three premises, namely, to witness is to be present, that which is witnessed must be available, and witnessing requires a record or representation of what has been witnessed.
Taking each of these in turn we have had to define presence, availability and representation to reflect what these means for Dasein.

We began by describing presence as an active phenomenon and treating it as readiness to encounter other beings (entities). In this respect it shares many of the characteristics with familiarity. Accepting that presence is directed at the world, it then possesses intentionality. Intentionality connects us to the world and when we witness something we ‘inherit’ this intentionality, so that the physiological and psychological states associated with witnessing are similarly intentional.

Next we considered the nature of the things (beings) we witness. Again by definition they must be available, proximal, and ready-to-hand. We then equated our experience of their availability with Gibson’s concept of affordance, which we have extended beyond the natural world of surfaces and edges to include many aspects of our human-made worlds.

Finally, the third aspect of this discussion concerns the nature of the representation associated with witnessing. We adopted Clark’s distinction between strong (genuine) representation and weak representation to suggest that when we witness something it is associated with this latter form, while when we recall what we have witnessed we rely on the strong form as evidenced by the manipulation that these recollection are subject to. Again we extended this idea of Clark’s to suggest that the affordances themselves serve as an external representation, indeed a kind of recursive representation of themselves. While this suggestion may be anathema to affordance purists it does serve to connect the phenomenological with the cognitive.

This special issue of the journal AI & Society on Witnessed Presence has given us an opportunity to consider real world presence or to re-phrase this in Heideggerian language, it has disclosed the nature of presence and one of the consequences of being present in the world.

Acknowledgments
Sincere thanks to the reviewers of this paper and the editors of this special issue for their help in the preparation of this manuscript. Thanks also to Professor John Waterworth for his kind permission to reproduce figure 1.

Expand selection Contract selection

Acknowledgements

Sincere thanks to the reviewers of this paper and the editors of this special issue for their help in the preparation of this manuscript. Thanks also to Professor John Waterworth for his kind permission to reproduce figure 1.

References

Baños, R.M., Botella C., Alcañiz M. and Liaño V. (2004) Immersion and Emotion: Their Impact on the Sense of Presence. Cyberpsychology & Behaviour, 7(6): 734 -741.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932) Remembering. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Biocca, F. (1997) The cyborg's dilemma: progressive embodiment in virtual environments. Journal of Computer Mediated Communication, 3(2): no page numbers.
Braun, K.A., Ellis, R. and Loftus, E.F. (2002) Make My Memory: How Advertising Can Change Our Memories of the Past. Psychology and Marketing, 19(1): 1-23.
Brentano, F., 1995. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Translated by A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell and L. L. McAlister. Routledge, London.
Brogni, A., Slater, M. and Steed, A. (2003) More Breaks Less Presence. Proc. 6th Annual International Workshop on Presence, no page numbers.
Burt, C.D.B., Kemp, S. and Conway, M. (2001) What happens if you retest autobiographical memory 10 years on? Memory & Cognition, 29(1): 127-136.
Chemero, A. (2009) Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Clark, A. (1997a) The dynamical challenge. Cognitive Science, 21(4): 461–481.
Clark, A. (1997b) Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Clark, A. and Grush, R. (1999) Towards a cognitive robotics. Adaptive Behavior, 7(1): 5–16.
Cohen, G. (1989) Memory in the real world. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, East Sussex.
Cole, M. (1996) Cultural Psychology. Harvard University Press.
Conway, M.A. (2001) Sensory-perceptual episodic memory and its context: autobiographical memory. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Soc. London B., 356: 1375-1384.
Conway, M.A. (2003) Commentary: Cognitive-Affective mechanisms and processes in autobiographical memory, Memory, 11(2): 217-224.
de Souza, C. S., Prates, R. O. and Carey, T. (2000) Missing and declining affordances: are these appropriate concepts? Journal of the Brazilian Computer Society, 7(1): 26-34.
de Souza, C.S. (1993) The Semiotic Engineering Of User Interface Languages. International Journal of Man-Machine Studies, 39: 753–773.
Dreyfus, H. (1991) Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Dreyfus, H. (1996) The current relevance of Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology of embodiment. Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy. http://ejap.louisiana.edu/EJAP/1996.spring/dreyfus.1996.spring.html [last retrieved 11.01.2011]
Dreyfus, H. (2002) Intelligence without representation – Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation: The relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4): 367–383.
Dreyfus, H. L. and Wrathall, M.A. (2005) Introduction. In H.L. Dreyfus and M.A. Wrathall (Eds) A Companion to Heidegger. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, MA.
Fencott, C. (1999) Presence and the Content of Virtual Environments. Proc 2nd International Workshop On Presence. Essex, U.K., no page numbers.
Freeman, J., Lessiter, J., Keogh, E., Bond, F.W. and Chapman, K. (2004) Relaxation Island: Virtual, and Really Relaxing. Proc. 7th International Workshop on Presence, 67-72
Freeman, W. J. (1999) Societies of Brain. Laurence Elbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ.
Gaver, W. W. (1991) Technological Affordances. Proc. CHI '91. NY: ACM, 1991.
Gaver, W. W. (1992) The Affordances Of Media Space For Collaboration. Proc. CSCW ’92. NY: ACM Press, 17-24.
Gibson, J. J. (1986) The Ecological Approach To Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston.
Grèzes, J. and Decety, J. (2002) Does Visual Perception Of Object Afford Action? Evidence From A Neuroimaging Study. Neuropsychologia, 40: 212-222.
Harman, G. (2002) Tool Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects. Open Court, Chicago.
Hartson, H.R. (2003) Cognitive, Physical, Sensory and Functional Affordances In Interaction Design. Behaviour & Information Technology. 22(5): 315-338.
Heidegger, M. (1927/1962) Being and Time. (Translated by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson) Harper Collins, New York.
Heidegger, M. (1982) The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. (Translated by A. Hofstadter) Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Heidegger, M. (1985) History of the Concept of Time. Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Held, R. M. and Durlach, N. I. (1992) Telepresence. Presence: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments, 1(1): 109-112.
IJsselsteijn, W.A., de Ridder, H., Freeman, J. and Avons, S.E. (2000) Presence: Concept, determinants and measurement. Proceedings of the SPIE, 3959. Human Vision and Electronic Imaging V, 24-27 January 2000, San Jose, USA.
Lessiter, J., Freeman, J., Keogh, E. and Davidoff, J. (2001) A cross-media presence questionnaire: The ITC-Sense of Presence Inventory. Presence: Teleoperators & Virtual Environments, 10: 282-298.
Lewin, K. (1936) Principles of topological psychology. McGraw-Hill, New York.
Loftus, E. F. (1975) Leading Questions and The Eye-Witness Report. Cognitive Psychology, 7: 560-572
Loftus, E. F. (1979) The Malleability of Human Memory. American Scientist, 67: 312-320.
Loftus, E. F., Donders, K., Hoffman, H. G. and Schooler, J. W. (1989) Creating new memories that are quickly accessed and confidently held. Memory & Cognition, 17: 607-616.
Lombard, M. and Ditton, T. (1997) At the heart of it all: The concept of presence. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication, 3(2), no page numbers
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/1962) Phenomenology of Perception. (Trans. C. Smith) Routledge Classics, London.
Neisser, U. (1978) Memory: What are the important questions? In M. M. Gruneberg, Morris, P. and Sykes, R. (Eds.) Practical Aspects Of Memory. Academic Press, London. pp. 3-24.
Norman, D.A. (1988) The Psychology Of Everyday Things. Basic Books, New York.
Norman, D.A. (1999) Affordance, Conventions and Design. interactions, may + june: 38-42.
Nunez, D. and Blake, E.H. (2006) Learning, experience and cognitive factors in the presence experiences of gamers: An exploratory relational study. Presence: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments. 15(4): 373-380.
O’Regan, J.K. (1992) Solving the “Real” Mysteries of Visual Perception: The World as an Outside Memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46(3): 461-488
Revonsuo, A. (2006) Inner Presence. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Riva, G., Waterworth, J.A. and Waterworth, E.H. (2004) The Layers Of Presence: A Bio-Cultural Approach To Understanding Presence In Natural And Mediated Environments. Cyberpsychology & Behaviour, 7(4): 405-419.
Schloerb, D.W. (1995) A quantitative measure of telepresence. Presence: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments, 4: 64–80.
Schubert, T.W., Friedmann, F. and Regenbrecht, H.T. (2001) The experience of presence: Factor analytic insights. Presence: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments. 10(3): 266-281.
Schuemie, M.J., Van Der Straaten, P., Krijn, M. and Van Der Mast, C.A.P.G. (2001) Research on Presence in Virtual Reality: A Survey. CyberPsychology & Behaviour, 4(2): 183-201.
Shakespeare, W. (c. 1600) Hamlet. Available from http://shakespeare.mit.edu/hamlet/full.html [last retrieved 01.05.2010]
Slater, M. (2003) A note on presence terminology. Presence-Connect, (3)3. Available from: http://presence.cs.ucl.ac.uk/presenceconnect/articles/Jan2003/melslaterJan27200391557/melslaterJan27200391557.html [last retrieved 15.12.2010]
Stoffregen, T. A. (2000) Affordances and events. Ecological Psychology, 12: 1–28.
Turner, P. (2005) Affordance As Context. Interacting With Computers. 17(6): 787-800.
Turner, P. (2007) The Intentional Basis of Presence. Proc. 10th International Workshop on Presence, 127-134.
Turner, P. (2008a) Towards an Account of Intuitiveness. Behaviour and Information Technology. 27(6): 1-8.
Turner, P. (2008b) Being-with: A Study of Familiarity. Interacting with Computers. 20: 447-454.
Turvey, M. T. (1992) Affordances and prospective control: An outline of the ontology. Ecological Psychology, 4: 173–187.
Warren, W. H. (1984) Perceiving affordances: Visual guidance of stair-climbing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 10: 683–703.
Waterworth, J.A. and Waterworth, E.L. (2001) Focus, Sensus And Locus: The Three Dimensions Of Virtual Experience. Cyberpsychology & Behaviour, 4(2): 203-213.
Witmer, B.G., and Singer, M.J. (1998) Measuring Presence In Virtual Environments: A Presence Questionnaire. Presence: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments, 7(3): 225– 240.
Zahorik, P. and Jenison, R.L. (1998) Presence as being-in-the-world. Presence: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments, 7:

Expand selection Contract selection